Electronic Reserve Text: John Guillory, "Paradoxy"

All that is solid melts into air, all that is holy is profaned ....
-MARX AND ENGELS, Manifesto of the Communist Party

It has long been a received idea that the New Criticism depoliticized the study of literature by rejecting the significance of overtly political or philosophical ideas for the evaluation or interpretation of literary works, and by restricting the object of criticism to the text itself, supplemented by only so much contextual information as would enable the proper understanding of topical references or archaic usages. The received idea has been definitively revised by Gerald Graff's recent Professing Literature, which reconstructs the institutional history of criticism in the American university, within which the New Criticism established hegemony by the 1950s.20

    Graft emphasizes the fact that "the New Critics were originally neither aesthetes nor pure explicators but culture critics with a considerable 'axe to grind' against the technocratic tendencies of modern mass civilization" (149). In Graff's useful mapping of the literary academy in the 1930s and 40s, the New Critics represent a splinter group within the category of what Graff calls the "Generalists," those critics who saw the objectives of literary study as immediately social and edifying. These descendants of the bourgeois public sphere cohabited uneasily in the university with the philological specialists, who were likely to define their practice more narrowly as the accumulation of a specific kind of knowledge. Graff points out quite rightly that the emergence of the "literary critic" within the generalist faction did not imply a simple repudiation of the disciplinary style of the philologist, but rather the development of a more or less rigorous countermethodology of "interpretation" which could be put in the service of "Generalist" aims, the aims of cultural criticism. Therein lies the answer to the puzzle of the received idea, the sense in which it is both correct and seriously inaccurate; for the New Critics, "the point was to define these social and moral functions as they operated within the internal structure of literary works themselves" (148). This agenda is already implicit in Eliot's fetishizing of form, but as with Eliot it is difficult to see how form or "internal structure" can convey a critique of modernity unless it is in some way read as adversarial. The inability of form to express its own adversarial meaning is betrayed in Eliot's deliberate translation of tradition (fidelity to form) into orthodoxy (fidelity to doctrine).
Graff's analysis of how the New Criticism solved this problem argues initially for the implicitly critical nature of literary form: "These critics' very insistence on the disinterested nature of poetic experience was an implicit rejection of a utilitarian culture and thus a powerfully 'utilitarian' and 'interested' gesture" (149). Now this hypothesis converges in an interesting way upon a left critique of modernity such as we might find in Adorno, a convergence which is immediately suspicious. Granted that modernism produced both left and right critiques of modernity, does the difference between these critiques make no difference? We may suppose that if the New Critics ever passed through a pristine moment of faith in the social effects of disinterestedness per se, they would never have had to explicate the meaning of form in other than formal terms. But there is much evidence to suggest, as Graff goes on to insist, that literature was never entrusted to make its point by itself: "First generation New Critical explications of literature were rarely explications only: they were cultural and philosophical essays in which texts like 'The Canonization,' 'Sailing to Byzantium,' and the poems of Poe became allegorical statements about the dissociation of sensibility, technical rationality, the collapse of the Old South, or some other equally large theme" (150). After a certain point, however, the "allegory" tended to drop away, and "the argument that the politics of literature should be seen as part of its form modulated subtly into the idea that literature had no politics, except as an irrelevant extrinsic concern" (150). Presumably it is only at this point that the received idea becomes true, but true in a rather paradoxical sense. For is it not also a constituent of the received idea that the purging of the political from the study of literature has a tendentially conservative effect, conservative by default? What did it matter, then, when the "allegory" dropped away from the practice of New Critical reading if in any case that reading proved ten-dentially conservative?
Graff's historical account of the New Criticism raises an interesting question about the moment at which the allegory drops away (Graff dates it precisely to 1951, with the publication of Reuben Brower's Fields o[ Light), since that moment coincides with the triumph of the New Criticism in the university (150). It is also the moment (the decade following the war) when modernist poetry is irrevocably established in the curriculum (in our terminology, "canonized'). The connection between these several triumphs is extremely intimate, because a large part of the adversarial agenda of the New Criticism in the thirties and forties was expressed as a direct extension of Eliot's revisionary literary history, in the form of a double polemic on behalf of modernist poets and the metaphysicals. Graft observes that by the time Cleanth Brooks publishes The Well Wrought Urn (1947), it is no longer necessary for the New Critics to polemicize further on behalf of Eliot's or their own earlier revisionary judgments of English literary history. The same qualities that Eliot found primarily or only in minor poetry are now found in the works of the established literary canon. Eliot's narrative of English literary history as the story of a split between an orthodox minor tradition and a heterodox major line is thus displaced into allegorical explications of the "internal structures" of the canonical texts, which all exhibit the features of paradox, irony, or ambiguity formerly attributed specific:ally to the metaphysicals and the moderns. The question of what difference it makes when the larger historical allegory drops away is thus a question about the "moment" of the reassimilation of the alternative or "minor" tradition into the established canon, and about the effectiveness of that reassimilation in establishing a new institutional hegemony for the New Criticism. It is a question of how the socioinstitutional conditions of literary criticsm itself are registered in the allegorical reading of literary structure. We can put this question in more concrete terms, terms that recognize the peculiar significance of The Well Wrought Urn as a text which defines the moment in question. If that text discovers that all canonical literature (or literature per se) speaks the "language of paradox," it still reads paradox as the evidence of a "unity of experience" no longer available to dissociated moderns, though we moderns may continue to contemplate what we have lost in the experience of the literary artifact. What circumstances, then, will cause that historico-political meaning of paradox to disappear, while the thesis that poetic language is intrinsically paradoxical succeeds so spectacularly? I should like to argue that we will not be able to understand how paradox "modulates" (Graff's term) into an implicitly apolitical (purely formal) concept without recognizing that Brooks's concept is "ideological" in the sense I have already indicated, namely, that the explicit political significance of his concept of paradox cannot account for its political effects, a fact which is proven by the very ease with which the explicit political meaning drops away in the 1950s. The ideological effect rather inheres in the discrepancy between the level of doxa (what is unquestioned, impense') and what is openly adovcated, an "orthodoxy." What needs to be explained then, is not simply the relation of the poem to particular beliefs, political or otherwise, but the institutional status of literary criticism in relation to the socioeconomic conditions of modernity.
Let us recall, then, that in 1939, in the chapter of Modern Poetry and the Tradition entitled "Notes toward a Revised History of English Literature," Brooks can still reproduce almost exactly the judgments implicit in Eliot's criticism, an indebtedness Brooks later acknowledged in these terms:

I was particularly stimulated by two paragraphs in one of his essays on the metaphysical poets. In this brief passage, he suggested that the metaphysical poets were not to be regarded as a rather peculiar offshoot of English poetry, but had a deep, hidden connection with its central line of development. This, to me [was a] new way of looking at the tradition of English poetry.2~

The hiddenness of that connection, the peculiar centrality of a tradition which is perceived to be marginal-these are of course motifs with which we are very familiar. Yet it would be a mistake to find in Brooks's criticism only a replication of Eliot's literary historical motifs, as such a replication would not have sufficed in the 1930s to ground a new literary pedagogy. The pressure to produce such a pedagogic method is simply institutional. Eliot's cultural criticism presumes as its site of enunciation the "workshop" of the poet, or the journal of the authoritarian cultural critic. The New Criticism develops in the 1930s in competition with other pedagogic methods to which it also owes a considerable debt, chief among these the methodology developed by I. A. Richards. For Richards had already, in the 1920s, confronted the fact of modern "dissociation," and had produced a form of critical pedagogy more or less reconciled to the secularity presumed to characterize modernity. As we know, this pedagogy sought to place criticism on scientific grounds, a project whose immediate context is the logical positivism emergent between the wars. These circumstances are worth recollecting (if all too cursorily) because they suggest the heavy polemical burden initially borne by the New Criticism, the burden of a double antagonist: both modernity and the particular accommodations to modernity competing for hegemony in literary culture. We may invoke these antagonists by way of accounting for Brooks's rewriting of Eliot's literary history in Modern Poetry and the Tradition in order to demonize science: "We have argued... that the critical revolution in the seventeenth century which brought metaphysical poetry to an end was intimately bound up with the beginnings of the New Science.''22 This hypothesis was unnecessary to Eliot's narrative, but it is quite crucial to Brooks's. Aside from betraying the large epistemological anxieties to which literature has been periodically subject, it gives Brooks a way of apparently emptying the doctrinal content from every literary work, as a prolegomenon to the reading of the work. Hence the "heresy of paraphrase," as defined in The Well Wrought Urn:

The position developed in earlier pages obviously seeks to take the poem out of competition with scientific, historical, and philosophical propositions. The poem, it has been argued. does not properly eventuate in a proposition: we can only abstract statements from the poem, and in the process of abstraction we necessarily distort the poem itself.

This position is oddly enough very close to Richards's, in that it seems to regard every "proposition" with pretension to truth value as by definition a scientific proposition. If there exists any other kind of truth, it cannot by definition be expressed in the form of a proposition. Brooks's theory concedes a very great deal to the epistemological tyranny of science (really, to the positivist "philosophy of science" regnant between the wars), but only because that concession is strategic, because scientific truth has already been stigmatized as the origin of our dissociated modernity. The important point to note here is that when the "proposition" is conflared with the claim to scientific truth, then any proposition one might be tempted to derive from a poem can be stigmatized as putatively "scientific," as subject to the norms of scientific verification. It is not surprising, then, that all statements of any kind derived from a poem fall under the heading of "paraphrase."

    Clearly the object of this strategy is not simply to remove the poem from competition with scientific truth, but to remove certain other truths from that competition. These truths are no longer expressed as propositions or statements but are rather embodied in the form of the poem, in the very antagonism between poetry (or literature) and the epistemological bully whose name is science. This strategic indirection of an alternative non-scientific truth commits the poem to a kind of gestural aphasia, an aphasia repeated in the process of reading the poem. The teacher or interpreter of the poem can only point to the truth which must not be spoken, but the very unspokenness of that truth elevates it to a status vastly greater than that of scientific truth, which always falls to the level of mere fact. Perhaps even more important, the interpretire method enjoined by this theory can safely bypass what looks like statement in a poem, secure in the knowledge that its truth lies elsewhere, in certain aspects of its/corm, in what Brooks calls "paradox." If this form, the form of paradox, can then be given a certain meaning, we shall see that this meaning is curiously self-reflective: it is that paradox names the very condition by which the poem does not name the truth to which it nevertheless gestures. The condition of paradox is precisely the fact that a certain truth (doxa) stands alongside (para) the poem itself. We shall further see that this condition characterizes what was once a mode of historical existence, a relation to truth that is for Brooks pre-modern, but which now survives only in the structure of the literary arti-fact. In this way the paradox specific to any given poem recapitulates the historical narrative that subtends New Critical practice, making possible the "allegory" Graffdescribes as characteristic of early New Critical readings. Insofar as every successful poem achieves the condition of paradox, it annuls the specific statements which may appear to be asserted in the poem, and becomes a kind of hologrammic image of literature as a whole.
We may now demonstrate this hologrammic effect by considering at greater length Brooks's reading of a particular poem, "The Canonization," which also happens to be the poem he offers as exemplifying the principle of paradox in the chapter of The Well Wrought Urn entitled "The Language of Paradox." The subsequent history of criticism has transformed the title of the poem into a pun intended neither by Donne nor by Brooks; but the pun is a fortunate contingency, since what is at issue in the reading of "The Canonization" is nothing less than the reintegration of the "metaphysical" poets into the "central stream of the tradition": "One was to attempt to see, in terms of this approach, what the masterpieces had in common rather than to see how the poems of different historical periods differed-and in particular to see whether they had anything in common with the metaphysicals and with the moderns" (WWU, 193).23
The definition of paradox in this first chapter of The Well Wrought Urn entails, to begin with, the usual distinction between poetry and science: "There is a sense in which paradox is the language appropriate and inevitable to poetry. It is the scientist whose truth requires a language purged of every trace of paradox" (WWU, 3). This tells us not so much what paradox is, only that it is a sort of language antithetical to the sort of language science employs; yet we are also told that paradox is "intellectual" and "hard" and that it is not usually thought of as the "language of the soul." In taking over some of the characteristics of scientific language, paradox is already paradoxical; it already refuses to be defined as either the language of thought or the language of feeling. If paradox then coyly implies what Eliot would have considered to be the linguistic expression of an "associated sensibility," it can only embody a state of dissociation which has already set in, after "thought" and "feeling" are perceived as antithetical. The reconciliation of these two antitheses, which has rather a long pedigree in the Romantic tradition, and which communicates distantly with other contemporary notions of alienation, gives us the first historical meaning of paradox. But this sense of paradox can be further generalized along purely formal lines, as the reconciliation of any apparent antitheses. The latter concept underlies all three major tropes defining the rhetorical lexicon of the New Criticism:

One perhaps does not need to point out that the importance assigned to the resolution of apparently antithetical attitudes accounts for the emphasis in earlier pages on (1) wit, as an awareness of the multiplicity of possible attitudes to be taken toward a given situation; on (2) paradox, as a device for contrasting the conventional view of a situation, or limited and special view of it such as those taken in practical and scientific discourse, with a more inclusive view; and on (3) irony, as a device for definition of attitudes by qualification (WWU, 257)

It would seem, given this set of definitions, that wit and irony are only versions of paradox, and that paradox thus bears the ideological weight of the New Critical agenda, its generalization from the reading of one poem to the reading of every poem (the canon), and from the canon to the larger historical and political field.
When we come to the example of Donne's "The Canonization," the an-titheses in question are defined more narrowly in one sense, since they engage a theme specific to Donne's poem, but equally broadly in another sense, since this thematic concerns "the world":

The basic metaphor which underlies the poem (and which is reflected in the title) involves a sort of paradox. For the poet daringly treats profane love as if it were divine love. The canonization is not that of a pair of holy anchorites who have renounced the world and the flesh. The hermitage of each is the other's body; but they do renounce the world, and so their title to sainthood is cunningly argued. The poem is then a parody of Christian sainthood; but it is an intensely serious parody of a sort that modern man, habituated as he is to an easy yes or no, can hardly understand. (WWU, 11)

No one would deny that the distinction between the sacred and the profane constitutes the thematic infrastructure of the poem, or that the technique of "sacred parody" is characteristic of "metaphysical" lyric. But the easy translation of parody into paradox is occasioned by Brooks's interest, entirely on the surface here, of contrasting the experience related in the poem to the cruder experience of "modern man." It is worth underscoring the fact that what Graft calls the "allegorical" level of New Critical interpretation requires no effort at all to recover, is in fact too easy to recover. That level of interpretation is "ideological," but in the rather obvious sense in which television commercials make hyperbolic or irrelevant claims about the effects of their products which everyone recognizes as a design upon his or her desire. Yet it is by no means evident that recognizing this design completely annuls the effectiveness of the advertisement, since there may well be other effects which operate elsewhere than at the level of oven claims, at the level of aesthetic "form." In a similar way, one might say that Brooks's too obvious intention to make an invidious contrast between the modern world and the world of the metaphysicals distracts one from a certain kind of work which is being done at another level of the reading. And this discrepancy between the overt claim made for the experience of the poem and that other "level" of the reading recapitulates the very distinction which founds the reading, between the "statements" in the poem and the "paradox" which supposedly defines its structure.
Let us pursue the Brooksian allegory a little further: "To use the metaphor on which the poem is built, the friend represents the secular world which the lovers have renounced" (WWU, 11). In this statement the distinction between sacred and profane is rewritten as the distinction between sacred and secular. The latter concept introduces a distinction which is again patently evocative of historical processes, of "secularization" as a phenomenon which postdates the period of the poem: "What happens to Donne's lovers if we consider them 'scientifically', without benefit of the supernaturalism which the poet confers on them?" (WWU, 18). The concept of the "secular" governing the intrusion of a "scientific" perspective here is not exactly equivalent to the concept of the profane (the word "secular" in fact does not signify in Donne's time what it does today), since.it suggests an entire world from which the sacred has been evacuated. While one may construe the relation between the sacred and the profane as in some sense paradoxical in the poem, it is difficult to see how that paradox could operate where one of its terms is simply absent. In Donne's world there is profane space, but that world is not in our sense secular. Hence there is no question of a paradox in which the sacred and the secular are reconciled: "The lovers in becoming hermits, find that they have not lost the world, but have gained the world in each other, now a more intense, more meaningful world. The unworldly lovers thus become the most 'worldly' of all" (WWU, 15). If it is a question of secularization, of the "worldly" in our sense, how could there be any possibility of reconciliation between what are in fact two worlds, not two spaces within the world? The space of the profane always presumes the space of the sacred, else it is simply meaningless. The secular world, if that world is "modern," presumes rather the absence, or at least the marginalization, of the sacred. We would have to say, then, that the paradox overshoots its target, that it can at most extend to the antithesis between the sacred and the profane in Donne's world.
For Brooks the relation between two spaces in the poem can be signified unequivocally by the concepts of the sacred and the profane, or secondarily by the sacred and the secular. Even though the former distinction describes a certain aspect of Donne's world, it still may not be the primary referent in the poem, given the fact that the motif of sacred parody is not introduced until the penultimate stanza. Until that moment the spaces in the poem are organized by the distinction between public and private, the difference between the social space the speaker presently occupies and the social space from which he has withdrawn, the space of politics, business, war, etc. If this distinction is truly the organizing "antithesis" of the poem, one must concede as a matter of historical fact that in Donne's world the public space is indisputably valorized over the private, and that it is the very indis-putability of this hierarchy which the poem takes as socially given. The wit of the poem then consists in its mobilizing the assymetrical hierarchy of the sacred and the profane in a surprising way, by aligning the sacred with the private and the profane with the public. Such an alignment is not exactly paradoxical, since it does not argue that the antitheses are in any way reconciled; it rather reverses one hierarchical opposition, between the public and the private, by transposing upon it another, the profane and the sacred. The question confronting the reader at this point is whether to understand the valorization of private experience in the poem as straightforward or ironic. It is no small irony of Brooks's reading that it must assume that valorization to be unironic, a point made by Arthur Marotti in his recent John Donne, Coterie Poet, in direct response to long-standing New Critical or formalist interpretations of the poem:

In its original context, however, "The Canonization" communicated a very different message [than the one argued by Brooks]. Donne's readers knew that he was expressing his personal longing for the public world he pretended to scorn in this lyric and they would have read the poem as a more ironic, hence more aesthetically complex, work than the one the formalist critics and scholars utilizing literary and intellectual history have interpreted.24

In Marotti's reading the irony of the poem is at the expense of the speaker, who overcompensates for his withdrawal from the public world by hyperbolic claims for an erotic relationship. The sacred parody which Brooks reads as conveying an ironic superiority toward the "friend," and by extension toward the "modern" reader, is in this "contextual" interpretation a hyperbole which renders the poem "more ironic" when the site of ironized understanding is displaced to the "context." We need not pause here over the well-worn methodological issues raised by Marotti's distinction (between "formalist" and "anti-formalist" interpretation) in order to recognize the peculiar weakness of Brooks's allegory as an interpretation of the poem, an interpretation which violates a cardinal principle of New Critical reading by taking at face value what the speaker of the poem says, even by proposing an identification of the reader with that speaker. This depletion of the poem's irony nevertheless does not in the slightest vitiate the persuasiveness in historical context of Brooks's essay, the context of The Well Wrought Urn's programmatic rereading of the English literary tradition. This persuasiveness inheres not so much in the essay's generalizations about history, or about the desiccated secularity of modern life, as it does in its generalization of paradox as the "language of poetry." A second allegory emerges from behind, or is carried forward by the first, in which "The Canonization" somehow inscribes the essential condition of the poetic or the literary.
In the second allegory the historical thesis can indeed drop away, once it has done the work of transferring the epithet "sacred" from a historical period to the poem itself. The aura of the sacred is then transferred again to a certain social space accessible only in the reading of the poem. As we shall see, this social space replicates the space figured in the poem itself as a "hermitage," the space of religious withdrawal, or more narrowly as a "room":

And if no peece of Chronicle wee prove, We'll build in sonnets pretty roomes;
As well a well wrought urne becomes The greatest ashes, as halfe-acre tombes,
And by these hymnes, all shall approve Us Canoniz'd for Love:

Brooks explicates this passage as follows:
The poem is an instance of the doctrine which it asserts; it is both the assertion and the realization of the assertion. The poet has actually before our eyes built within the song the "pretty room" with which he says the lovers can be content. The poem itself is the well-wrought urn which can hold the lovers' ashes and which will not suffer in comparison with the prince's "half-acre tomb." (WWU, 17)

    It is a measure of just how effective this moment has been for the subsequent history of literary criticism that the great inconsistency of Brooks's attributing to the poem a "doctrine" which it unequivocally "asserts'' has been forgiven, if it has even been noticed. The point is not simply that the poem is an artifact, or that as an aesthetic utterance it excludes the kind of political assertion one would associate with the prince, with the social space of the political. The literary critical doctrine which the poem asserts, by virtue of the second allegory, really achieves its effect only by having followed so directly from the first; in this way the distinction between the sacred and the secular is carried over into a characterization, respectively, of the social space of literature and some other, antithetical social space.
If that other social space is thus to be defined as "secular," it would have to include in Brooks's terms virtually everything within the experience of modern life, the space which is perceived to be inherently hostile to literature. Conversely the space of literature is obviously not the same space as that of religious withdrawal-the "hermitage" of which Donne speaks-such as actually may survive in the modern world, and which secular culture suffers to exist because it is no longer significant enough to extinguish. Just as the sacred parody defined the space of erotic withdrawal in Donne's poem, so it defines the social space of the reading of the poem in the second allegory. This space is unmistakably institutional-it is where literature is read, the site of Brooks's address to the professors of literature: "The urns are not meant for memorial purposes only, though that often seems to be their chief significance to the professors of literature" (WWU, 21). The ad-dressee here is specifically the philologist, with whom the New Critic contended for hegemony in the university, and against whom Brooks directs a running polemic in The Well Wrought Urn. The effect of this polemic is not simply to rehearse once again the imaginary identification of literary culture with the clergy but to redefine the social space of literary culture as necessarily institutional. The school becomes the site at which the practice of reading can be cultivated in such a way as to preserve the cultural capital of literature (signified in the Brooksian allegory as a kind of sacredness), just because its social space can be conceived as a space of deliberate and strategic withdrawal, as the withdrawal of literary culture from "the world."
The aura of sacredness which is communicated first to the poem and then to the social space in which the poem is read defines that space not simply as an "elsewhere," but as transcendent, the latter because that space acquires the auratic properties of the sacred. In the same way the truth the poem communicates becomes transcendent, and its refusal to speak directly, to assert propositions, is the guarantor of its possession of that other kind of truth, a "paradoxical" truth. The truth of every poem thus retreats before the act of interpretation; our arrival in its pretty room discovers an empty shrine, but a shrine nevertheless. The poem enjoins upon us the recognition of the externality of dogma and conceals from us the fact that we are already within its truth, that its truth is this externality: the poem as paradogmatic text. In this sense every poem becomes an image of the very institutional space in which it is read, a perfect mirror in the imaginary of that space, alerting the company of professional readers that the retreat of literary culture into the university can be understood as a kind of transcen-dence of the cultural conditions of modernity. This is Brooks's solution to the same problem which Leavis hoped to solve by reconstructing literary culture as an incognito clergy-but a very different solution.
It is also a solution fraught with contradictions, the most important of which is registered by the very ambiguity of the "urn" as a figure for the poem. While that figure does convey straightforwardly both the artifactual nature of the poem and its sacred aura, it offers a much less straightforward figure for the paradogmatic status of the literary work. If the urn were merely empty, that would suggest that its contents (its doctrine) were elsewhere, in a relation of transcendence to the (secular, scientific) doctrines which circulate as truth in the modern world. But the urn contains the ashes of something no longer living, and thus the figure stumbles unwittingly on the very social conditions for which it attempted to compensate: the perceived decline in the cultural significance of literature itself, the perceived marginality of literary culture to the modern social order. It would not do for Brooks to represent the truth toward which literature gestures as, in the terms of his allegory, mere ashes. Brooks is sufficiently aware of this implication of his allegory to attempt a confiation of Donne's "well wrought urn" with the urn in Shakespeare's '"The Phoenix and the Turtle," which urn, as it happens, contains the ashes of a phoenix: '"The urn to which we are summoned, the urn which holds the ashes of the phoenix, is like the well-wrought urn of Donne's 'Canonization' which holds the phoenix-lovers' ashes: it is the poem itself" (WWU, 21). Paradox has a doctrinal content after all, and Brooks cannot quite resist hinting at the doctrine he has in mind by offering as his privileged examples of paradox two biblical citations: "He who would save his life, must lose it,'' and '"The last shall be first" (WWU, 18). Here again, however, the hint is too blatant to be effective in its own terms, and the truth of the paradoxes in question beg to be read otherwise, perhaps as: '"he who would save the truth claims of literature must give them ups; and '"literary culture, though it may appear to be marginal, has now found a site at which it can exercise renewed power." The rebirth of the phoenix thus signifies the Eliot-like wish-fulfillment fantasy of a return to Christian orthodoxy; but that wish drops away virtually as soon as it is expressed and the phoenix rises instead as the figure for a resurgent literary culture, a '"new criticism" which establishes hegemony in the university by displacing the philologists, whose relation to literature was merely '"memorial," merely the preservation of the ashes of literary culture.

Doxy

With someone like you,
a pal good and true
I'd like to leave it all behind,
and go and find
Some place that's known to God alone,
Just a spot to call our own.
We'll find perfect peace,
where joys never cease,
Out there beneath a kindly sky,
We'll build a sweet little nest,
somewhere in the West,
And let the rest of the world go by.
-J. KEIRN BRENNAN, "Let the Rest of the World Go By"

It remains to be seen whether the retreat of literary culture to the university was really strategic. I would argue that Brooks betrays considerable ambiv-alence about the strategic withdrawal of literary culture to the confines of the academy whenever he reverts to Eliot's revisionary narrative of literary history: "A history of poetry from Dryden's time to our own might bear as its subtitle 'The Half-Hearted Phoenix'." (WWU, 20). What could this possibly mean if not that one implication of the reading of "The Canonization" is that much of English literature after Dryden is defective in terms of wit, ambiguity, paradox? The history of English literature is the history of the decline of literary culture itself. The momentary reassertion of the radically revisionist construction of the English literary canon thus stands in uneasy relation to the programmatic agenda of reading the major canonical poets "as one has learned to read Donne and the moderns" (WWU, 193).2s If the revisionist canon was the basis for a cultural jeremiad against modernity, a jeremiad in which the authority of literary culture was pitted against competing modern cultural authorities (whatever these may be), the programmatic attempt to demonstrate the continuity of every canonical English writer with the metaphysicals on the one hand, and the moderns on the other, was the strategic imperative of a more narrowly institutional campaign, a campaign for hegemony within the university.
Surely one of the more widely accepted received ideas about New Critical pedagogy has been that its success in the university was in part an effect of its suitability for the new, postwar university constituency of college students. Graff remarks, for example, that in addition to its larger ambition of counteracting the effects of "cultural fragmentation,"

putting the emphasis on the literary text itself had a more humble advantage: it seemed a tactic ideally suited to a new, mass student body that could not be depended on to bring to the university any common cultural background-and not just the student body but the new professors as well, who might often be only marginally ahead of the students. The explicative method made it possible for literature to be taught efficiently to students who took for granted little history. (173)

This is carefully worded and does not claim for New Critical pedagogy much more that its being at the right place at the right time. It would be a mistake to conclude on the basis of its resounding success that the technique of close reading was designed with the "mass student body" in view. Brooks and Warren's Understanding Poetry, for example, was first published in 1938, at a time when the university was still a very exclusive institution, when one could still assume the relative cultural and class ho-mogeneity of its constituency. There is no reason to assume that the basic principles of New Critical pedagogy were not formulated in a context highly sympathetic to elitist notions of High Culture. The version of formalism espoused by the New Critics never assumed that the readers of literature should be other than very well educated, else it would be difficult to see how these readers could follow the historical allegory continually being invoked in early New Critical interpretive essays. Even as late as The Well Wrought Urn, Brooks remarks that an apparently accessible poem such as Gray's Elegy is not so intelligible to modern readers as it may seem, because so much of the poem's meaning depends on allusions to work which is no longer familiar: "How important they [allusions] are may be judged by the response to the poem made by an audience which is really completely unaware of them: our public school system, it may be said, is rapidly providing such an audience for the purposes of making such a test" (WWU, 107). If the technique of close reading proved so congenial to the graduates of this same public school system, this fact presents a historical problem which is on the face of it not easy to explain.
Let us first of all acknowledge that for the New Critics the language of poetry, and of literature in general, was intrinsically difficult. This was not a difficulty which could be removed by the glossing of sources, or by recourse to information about the author's life or beliefs; it was a difficulty which did not disappear in the process of interpretation so much as it was confirmed. One may go further than this and say that difficulty itself was positively valued in New Critical practice, that it was a form of cultural capital, just by virtue of imparting to cultural objects a certain kind of rarity, the very difficulty of apprehending them. How, then, could this notion of difficulty survive the transformation of the New Criticism into a pedagogy which was disseminated far beyond the university, which penetrated even into the high schools and the grammar schools? The success of the New Criticism in the school system did not entail discarding the notion of poetry's difficulty for the contrary notion of its simplicity; rather, it was the notion of difficulty itself which became capable of wide dissemination, which became in a certain sense "popular."
If "difficulty" names the condition of poetic language more specifically signified by the terms "paradox," "ambiguity," or "wit," the valorization of difficulty as the general quality of poetic language was always an integral part of the New Critical agenda of canonizing the modernist poets. This project was not easy to accomplish, precisely because the notion of difficulty circulated between the wars as a negative criterion of judgment, as the basis for the resistance to modernist poetry. It was difficulty itself which had to be rehabilitated by invoking the precedent of the metaphysicals. The revaluation of difficulty on behalf of both metaphysicals and moderns is a consistent objective of The Well Wrought Urn, from which I extract the following exemplary polemical statements:

The question of what poetry communicates, if anything, has been largely forced upon us by the advent of "modern" poetry. Some of that poetry is admittedly highly difficult-a great deal of it is bound to appear difficult to the reader of conventional reading habits, even in spite of the fact-actually, in many cases, because of the fact-that he is a professor of literature.
For this reason, the difficult moderns are often represented as untraditional and generally irresponsible ....
The question, however, allows only one honest answer: modern poetry (if it is really poetry, and, at its best, it is really poetry), communicates whatever any other poetry communicates. (WWU, 67)

Much modern poetry is difficult. Some of it may be difficult because the poet is snobbish and definitely wants to restrict his audience, though this is a strange vanity and much rarer than Mr. Eastman would have us think. Some modern poetry is difficult because it is bad .... Some modern poetry is difficult because of the special problems of our civilization. But a great deal of modern poetry is difficult for the reader simply because so few people, relatively speaking, are accustomed to reading poetry as poetry....
Now the modern poet has, for better or worse, thrown the weight of the responsibility upon the reader. The reader must be on the alert for shifts of tone, for ironic statement. He must be prepared to accept a method of indirection. He is further expected to be reasonably well acquainted with the general tradition-literary, political, phiolsophical, for he is reading a poet who comes at the end of a long tradition .... (WWU, 76)

It would be disingenuous not to admit that in some respects this polemic is as viable now as it was when Brooks and the New Critics first advanced it; but this is not to say that the polemic is incapable of being read in historical context. The question before us is not whether difficulty should be a positive or negative criterion of value-one assumes that difficulty justifies itself, like anything else, in the specificity of its circumstancesrebut what difficulty means in a given context of its deployment as a concept. I have quoted Brooks's polemic at length in order to appreciate the sliding status of difficulty as a quality at once peculiar to the practice of modernist poetry and yet somehow characteristic of poetry in general, of "poetry as poetry." I would suggest that in possessing this (paradoxical?) quality of peculiarity and generality, the concept of difficulty corresponds to the waffling in Brooks's judgment between the narrow canon of metaphysicals and moderns authorized by Eliot, and the much larger "traditional" canon, which is identical to the established literary curriculum in the university. The very difficulty of demonstrating the difficulty of much "traditional" poetry accounts for the strenuous polemic of The Well Wrought Urn, since Brooks must convince his readers both that the difficulty of modernist poetry is justified and that all poetry is inherently difficult-the former proposition by means of the latter.26
The literary historical context of Brooks's valorization of difficulty has been persuasively established in a recent article by Craig S. Abbott entitled "Modern American Poetry: Anthologies, Classrooms, and Canons," whose conclusions I here incorporate.27 Abbott reminds us that there already existed by the 1920s a fairly well established canon of "modern" American poets, whose works were extensively anthologized, as well as taught in the high schools and colleges. These figures were not the familiar titans of modernism but rather "such poets as Vachel Lindsay, Amy Lowell, Edgar Lee Masters, and Carl Sandburgmpoets not thought especially difficult then or now" (209). The point of recollecting these names here is neither to emphasize once again the contingency of the process of canon formation, nor to defend the modernist canon which prevailed in the end, but rather to understand the basis for the resistance to the kind of modernism espoused by the New Critics. For the poets who were so consistently anthologized in the 1920s and 1930s, as well as taught in the schools, were perceived to be in every way modern. That modernity was characterized, however, by its affirmative quality, by its embrace of a culture which it regarded optimistically as progressive, democratic, and "popular" in an entirely positive sense. Such a relation to modernity demanded of cultural works themselves that they be generally accessible, and therefore that they not be difficult. It was on the basis of this "popular" modernism that the work of Eliot, Pound, or Stevens could be dismissed precisely for its quality of difficulty.
The conflict between a "popular" and a "high" modernism engages issues rather larger than can be treated here, and hence I will be content with making a somewhat more limited point: The meaning of simplicity and difficulty as qualities of poetic language cannot be resolved into unambiguous politiS;al oppositions. Popular modernism's affirmation of the "democratic" was also, at least in its American version, intensely chauvinistic, as well as complicitous with aspects of mass culture whose effects tended toward the domination of what Adorno and Horkheimer called the "culture industry." Conversely the reactionary elitism of so much high modernism could stimulate the production of genuinely adversarial cultural forms, an ambiguity that tends to obscure the differences between left and right versions of modernism at the level of form. If this ambiguity is only too familiar now, as the occasion of an interminable analysis of "modernism," we need not adjudicate the positions within this debate in order to recognize that the very existence of a "popular" literary modernism testified to a temporary blurring of the cultural capital embodied by literature and by the artifacts of mass culture. Hence the anthologies of the period, as Abbott points out, included as representative modern poems works such as Joyce Kilmer's "Trees," or even Katherine Lee Bates's "America the Beautiful" (216, 218)-works which it is difficult to regard now as anything other than kitsch, perhaps the least interesting "popular" artifacts of the twentieth century.
One might hypothesize that literature and mass culture could converge in this way in part because the linguistic capital traditionally acquired by the study of literature-Standard English-really was by the period in question very efficiently distributed at the lower levels of the school system to a very large percentage of the population. In other words, when Standard English (as the capital conveyed by a literary curriculum) became the possession of nearly everyone with a grade-school education, it coincided in the scope of its distribution with mass culture itself. In that circumstance the redundancy of the literary curriculum at the level of the university could become the occasion of a struggle over what kind of cultural capital was to be produced by literary study at that level. The argument for the linguistic simplicity of literature became a losing argument in that context just because it could not establish a sufficiently marked difference between the literary curriculum of the university and the curriculum at the lower levels of the school system. The argument for the linguistic difficulty of literature, on the other hand, revalued literature as the cultural capital of the university by reading it in a new way, as the embodiment of a language distinct in its difficulty, and thus by implication providing a different kind of linguistic capital from that conveyed by the literary curriculum at the lower levels of the school system. If this fact is hard to see in historical retrospect, that is because the valuation of difficulty in New Critical practice never had to be expressed, and could not be expressed, as the devaluation of Standard English itself. These two languages were not antithetical but rather coexisted as languages which were cultivated in different institutional spaces, at different levels of the school system. There was no question of any opposition between these languages, because one was spoken while the other was more or less exclusively written, a language embodied in literature as the New Critics defined it, a language which required interpretation. The valorization of difficulty thus entailed no derogation of Standard English but rather a renewed and intensified attack upon mass culture, precisely in order to distinguish the capital embodied in literary texts from the literary simulacra circulating as "popular modernism." As a result of the New Criticism's success in installing a modernist canon of difficult poets the works of popular modernism fell precipitously to the level of mass culture.
This effect could be achieved without advertising literature itself as the exclusive capital of an elite class, even if in practice the university was open only to a very small group within the society. It is worth recalling, then, that while the protocols of New Critical reading were established long before the universities opened their doors to a somewhat larger constituency after the Second World War, these protocols were not substantially altered by the increased size and diversity of that constituency. In discovering that literature was intrinsically difficult, these new students also discovered at the same moment why it needed to be studied in the university. The intrinsic difficulty of literary language marked precisely the distinction between High Cultural artifacts and mass cultural artifacts, but the important point here is that this distinction also defined the social spaces appropriate to the consumption of these cultural artifacts. This is the reason why the crypto-religious polemic of the New Critics against the secularity of modern life could drop away in the 1950s: that polemic could be received as a polemic against mass culture per se. The features of this polemic are not difficult to recover in such a text as The Well Wrought Urn, since the properties of "secularity" are confused throughout that text with the denigration of mass culture. But in an appendix refuting the "cultural relativism" of Frederick Pottle's recently published Idiom of Poetry, Brooks develops a longer and more explicit polemic against the depravity of mass culture. Pottle's cautious entertainment of a skepticism about the possibility of grounding the value judgments which distinguish High Culture from Low provokes in Brooks the sense of an imminent crisis in the humanities: "The issue is nothing less than a defense of the Humanities in the hard days that lie ahead" (WWU, 235). So far from eschewing judgment, then, Brooks presents the agenda of the New Criticism as expressly evaluative: "For critical relativism wins its simplicity and objectivity only at the sacrifice of the whole concept of literature as we know it. For what is the sensibility of our age? Is there any one sensibility? Do we respond to T. S. Eliot, Dashiell Hammett, Mary Roberts Rinehart, or Tiffany Thayer?" (WWU, 232). The necessity of judgment here is not the necessity of making discriminations within the canon of literature (such discriminations as Eliot's criticism continually advanced). Literature rather presents a united front, in the form of its intrinsic difficulty, against the artifacts of mass culture, and it is along this front that a defensive posture must be maintained: "Tied in with language may be a way of apprehending reality, a philosophy, a whole world-view" (WWU, 236). Not to maintain the distinction of poetic language would be tantamount to crediting the sensibility, in Brooks's sensational example, of the "young lady who confesses to raptures over her confessions magazine" (WWU, 233). While it is unlikely that the young lady in question ever bothered to compare her confession magazines with the great works of literature, the fact that Brooks must do so, and must arrive at the obvious conclusion about the respective values of these artifacts, suggests that he is really responding to a certain stage in the development of mass culture, a stage in which such a rapprochement of literature with mass culture as that embodied in "popular modernism" is no longer desirable for literary culture.

    If she had been asked, the reader of the confession magazines would no doubt have conceded the cultural superiority of literature, whether or not she ever felt inclined to read any works so designated. Therein lies the peculiar power of mass culture, since the waning cultural centrality of literary works in the face of new mass cultural forms never entailed a denial of the nominally superior value of literature. In this context one may appreciate the historical irony of the later reappearance of "The Canonization" as an exemplary text for explication in the fourth edition of Understanding Poetry (1976). There Donne's poem is contrasted not with secular, scientific culture, its antagonist in The Well Wrought Urn, but with a lyric from Tin Pan Alley called "Let the Rest of the World Go By." The choice of a "popular song from the 1920s" may reflect a certain High Cultural disconnection from popular culture, but it is more likely that the song is standing in rather coyly for more recent music, whose lyrics would only make the comparison with "The Canonization" more embarrassing: "The reader may question the propriety of comparing this massive poem with the flimsy little lyric from Tin Pan Alley quoted above on page 130. Surely one does not need to bring up a howitzer in order to annihilate a gnat.''28 There follows nevertheless a rather painstaking demonstration of the superiority of Donne's poem to the gnat-like popular song. The very belatedness of this polemic attests, however, to the persistence of the gnat, which is only a gnat in the hopeful perspective of its determined opponents, those who, as Brooks writes in The Well Wrought Urn, resist rather than give in to "the spirit of the age" (WWU, 235).
In its immense capaciousness, the mass culture of modernity never coveted the institutional space to which literary culture retreated. In that space a polemic against mass culture could be developed and blandly received by a generation of university students who willingly credited the cultural capital of literature, who learned to recognize the superiority of literature to mass cultural artifacts, but who continued to consume both kinds of arti-facts in the distinct spheres of their consumption. It may be said that "minority culture" came to be identified with the social space of the school, but it would be more accurate to say that it was internalized as a mode olccon-sumption in the graduate of the university. The capacity to experience the social space of the schools and the social space of mass culture as disjunct effectively institutionalized two modes of consumption, one consequence of which was to make literary works more difficult to consume outside the school? The polemic on behalf of the difficulty of literary language, and against the degraded simplicity of mass culture, did not have to be aimed at an audience of the socially elite, only university students, whoever they might be. It was even possible, after its triumph in the university, for New Critical pedagogy to be disseminated at the lower levels of the school system, since it was only necessary, in order to maintain the cultural capital of the literary curriculum, for the constitutive difficulty of literary language to be asserted there as well. We may fairly describe the effect of New Critical pedagogy as "paradoxical," since its most strenuous effort to impose a divorce between literary culture and mass culture produced in the end a curious kind of rapprochement. If this cultual detente does not represent an "association of sensibility," its submission to a certain cultural logic of inclusiveness renders unintentionally ironic such Brooksian attempts to characterize modernity as the following:

But if Donne could have it both ways, most of us, in this latter day, cannot. We are disciplined in the tradition of either-or, and lack the mental agility-to say nothing of the maturity of attitude-which would allow us to indulge in the finer distinctions and the more subtle reservations permitted by the tradition of both-and. Flesh or spirit, merely a doxy or purely a goddess (or alternately, one and then the other), is more easily managed in our poetry, and probably, for that matter, in our private lives. But the greater poems of our tradition are more ambitious in this matter: as a consequence, they come perhaps nearer the truth than we do with our ordinary hand-to-mouth insights. (WWU, 81)

When the choice is between literary culture and mass culture, however, there is no question of "both-and." There is no question of which might be represented as a goddess, which by the doxy; the example of the woman absorbed in her confession magazines confirms that. If mass culture can be stigmatized by association with the lurid taste of the female consumer, literary culture on the other hand becomes the site of a certain kind of worship, not of a goddess, but of its own version of transcendence, the experience to be found only in reading "the greater poems of our tradition." How very ironic, then, that neither the polemic against secularity nor the polemic on behalf of Eliot's canonical choices proved capable of imposing Brooks's "either-or" upon the generation of postwar readers. The effect of New Critical pedagogy was rather to produce a kind of recusant literary culture, at once faithful to the quasi-sacred authority of literature but paying tribute at the same time to the secular authority of a derogated mass culture. For the recusants the artifacts of mass culture might be consumed with a certain guilt, or a certain relief; but for those whose allegiance was sworn to the secular authority, that culture provided everything there was to consume.