![]() |
Electronic
Reserve Text: Chapter 1 from Matthew Jordon, Milton and Modernity 'Born to command and not to obey': Milton and the Political Force of Liberal Humanism Asserting the legitimacy of executing Charles I, Milton declared, with typical force: No man who knows
ought, can be so stupid to deny that all men naturally 'were borne free,
being the image and resemblance of God himself, and were by privilege
above all the creatures, born to command and not to obey. The texts in which Milton elaborated the implications of this premise have caused him to stand for many as 'the major intellectual spokesman' of the English Revolution.(1) In William Haller's judgement, 'His pamphlets, their influence enhanced and sustained by the poems which grew out of his revolutionary experience, would become one of the main channels by which Puritan revolutionary ideas in their most dynamic form would reach the age of John Locke.'(2) |
|
Certainly
Locke, whose Two Treatises of Government have earned him general
recognition as a founding father of liberal political thought, is in accord
with Milton in his fundamental assumption of the natural freedom of man.(3)
Near the opening of the Second Treatise Locke declares that 'To
understand political power aright, and derive it from its original, we
must consider what estate all men are naturally in, and that is, a state
of perfect freedom to order their actions, and dispose of 'their possessions
and persons as they think fit' (2T §4). Part of this freedom was
the right of each man to execute on his own behalf the law of nature,
an objective guide to right conduct recognizable by rational reflection
on the design of the universe, 'the material element of the
[20] may be restrained from invading others' rights, and from doing hurt to ' one another, and the law of Nature be observed, which willeth the peace; and preservation of all mankind, the execution of the law of Nature is : in that state put into every man's hands'. Likewise Milton, rendering his account of the origins of government in the form of an historical: narrative, refers to 'This autoritie and power of self-defence and preservation' against 'what was violated against peace and common right. ... being originally and naturally in everyone of them.' However, there are, as Locke puts it, 'inconveniences' in this 'state of nature'. Not only; is there the possibility that some men will be guilty of 'invading' the; rights of others, but there is the further danger that in judging what action to take in response men will be 'partial to. themselves and their friends' and too harsh towards others. Milton, too, recognizes the problems that would arise if 'each man should be his own partial judge'. ' Thus, as Locke puts it, 'civil government is the proper remedy'. An end is put to
the state of nature, states Milton, when men agree 'to ordain e som
authoritie, that might restrain by force and punishment what; was violated
against peace and common right' (2T §7 and 13; 'CPW 3.199). However, giving up the power personally to execute the law of nature is not the end of the freedom which is the essence of man as God has I made him, because 'it is not the end of the power to judge whether those charged with 'the responsibility of ruling, or executing the law of nature, are acting in accord with this law. For Locke, 'government has no other end but the preservation of property', defined a little later as the people's 'lives, liberties and estates, which I call by the general name -property', and 'The people shall be judge' of whether this trust has be,en kept (2T §94, 123, 240). 'Common right' predates and exists independently of the sovereign. Thus, even once magistrates were established they o remained accountable. The need for accountability underlies Milton's account, in Tenure, of how, since the power to execute justice 'left absolute in thir hands' (that is to say, unrestricted by specific laws) proved a 'temptation' to the first magistrates and 'perverted them at length to injustice and partialitie', the people found they had to frame laws so that 'man, of whose failing they had proof, might no more rule: over them, but law and reason abstracted as much as might be from personal errors and frailties' (CPW 3.199-200). According'to Locke, any power which is' not limited along these lines is 'no form of civil government at all' and is indeed worse than the state of nature, since a man' subject to such power is denied a right of redress:
Although we may not express the idea in terms of the structure and design of the universe, the notion that government is founded in law and accountable to the people seems commonsensical to us. This is a measure of how deeply ingrained the assumptions of liberal humanism have become. But the notion of a 'people' independent of political power yet entitled to call it to account is in fact historically specific, as is -demonstrated by the views of the Royalist Sir Robert Filmer, whose Patriarcha is described by Gordon Schochet as 'a concise statement of the traditional political beliefs that had to be overcome before constitutional liberalism could become a dominant ideology'.(5) Filmer was fundamentally opposed to the idea of an original natural liberty because his theory of political obligation was founded in Genesis, specifically in the beliefs that Adam's fatherly power was political in kind, that it was absolute because it consisted in a power of life and death over members of the family he ruled, and that all earthly government was ultimately derived from Adam's rule and shared its fatherly nature.(6) This is by no means representative of all political thought prior to the seventeenth century. Furthermore, Filmer is unusual even among patriarchalist and royalist theorists in basing a systematic theory of political obligation on Genesis, an effort which Locke demolished in his First Treatise.(7) The strength of the patriarchalist view of society was not essentially propositional but a matter of a 'cast of mind', intuitively convincing to many who lived in a society characterized by the exercise of paternal power, which the Stuarts and their supporters sought to exploit (with marked if posthumous success in the case of Eikon Basilike, supposedly written by Charles I himself).(8) Thus, in a speech to parliament in 1609, James I had the following to say about the relation between the king, his subjects and their property: [22]
...as a natural father, although he may be too harsh, too wicked, and even too cruel, cannot be removed by his children without the greatest crime, so it is not right that he who plays the role of public [23] parent, although he may oppress his subjects with burdensome and, unjust rule, be killed without the crime of parricide. Indeed as a 'father does not stop being a father, although he exercises the right of a father's power over his children too severely, so the king who exercises his power over his subjects too harshly does not lose the title, Father of his Country, as Justinianus says.(14 )
For Milton and Locke, on the other hand, individual liberty is, if not, the supreme value, then at least the indispensable precondition for the realization of the ultimate ends of human life.(17) In this emphasis they
are far removed from Hobbes, whose Leviathan, despite its advocacy of vesting absolute power in the hands of the sovereign, is now regarded by many as a classic text of early liberalism.(18) Insofar as they see government 'as a human affair which can be understood as the rational remedy for a governmentless state, both Milton and Locke share 'artificialist' terms of reference with Hobbes. However, Hobbes was the architect of an attempt to subvert the radical potential of contract theory, associated as this was with arguments for limitations on the power of governments.(19) Fundamental to this attempt is Hobbes's apparent neutralization of the subersive potential of appeals to the law of nature. For Hobbes, desire is the measure of good and evil: 'whatsoever is the object! of any mans Appetite or Desire; that is it, which he for his part calleth Good; And the object of his Hate, and Aversion, Evill.' Freedom does not consist in the recognition of an objective moral law, but amounts to the liberation of desire from external constraint, a state of affairs about which, as Hobbes stresses, there is nothing. distinctively human or moral. Liberty, for Hobbes, refers not to a quality of the subject but to the nature of its circuI1;lstances. It is, he asserts, 'Absurd, Insignificant, and Nonsense' to talk of A Free Subject; A free-Will; or any Free, but free from being hindred by opposition'. It is not a function of reason and so 'may be applyed no lesse to Irrationall, and Inanimate creatures, than to Rationall; (Lev. 120 / 24, 113 / 19, 261 / 107). Since there are no moral constraints on behaviour, 'during the time i men live without a common Power to keep them all in awe, they are in that condition which is called Warre; and such a warre, as is of every man, against every man'. It is a situation in which 'virtue' is given a Machiavellian twist: 'Force, and Fraud, are in warre the two Cardinall vertues.' Thus in the state of nature the life of man is, famously, 'solitary, poore, nasty, brutish, and short'. 'The 'condition of meer Nature, that is to say, of absolute Liberty... is Anarchy, and the condition: of Warre'. For Hobbes, self-preservation is paramount. Consequently, each man has a 'RIGHT OF NATURE' to do 'anything' in the cause: of 'the preservation of his own nature'. Given that 'there is nothing he [a man] can make use of, that may not be a help unto him, in preserving his life against his enemyes; It followeth, that in such a condition, every man has a Right to every thing; even to one anothers body' (Lev. i 185 / 62, 188 / 63, 186 / 62, 395 / 186, 189-90 / 64). Passages such as this would seem to be the reason that Locke pointedly places his dis- i cussion of the state of nature and the state of war in different chapters i of his Second Treatise. (Milton's state of nature is not so clearly defined in opposition to a doctrine which would deprive men of what he saw!
as their inherent rights.) Thus Locke asserts 'the plain difference i between the state of Nature and the state of war, which however some i men have confounded, are as far distant as a state of peace, goodwill, mutual assistance, and preservation; and a state of enmity, malice, violence and mutual destruction are one from another'. People are 'equal, and independent' because all belong to God and so no one has the right to domineer over anyone else (2T §19, §6). For Hobbes, by contrast, equality is a function of the fact that although there may be differences between men in physical strength or mental acuity, no claims can be based on these differences because 'the weakest hath strength enough: to kill the strongest', and (a little dry wit here) every man 'is contented with his share' of wisdom (Lev. 183-4 / 60-1). The law of nature
figures in Hobbes solely as a means of strengthening the sovereign.
On the one hand, it appears as a set of 'prudential maxims which will
recommend themselves by their logical force to any man desirous of avoiding
violent death', thus reducing 'the natural law I to counsels of self-preservation'.(20)
The 'Fundamentall Law of Nature [26] same reason a third, to punish the second; and so continually without end, to the Confusion, and Dissolution of the Commonwealth' (Lev. 297 / 128, 367 / 169). Such a vision of infinite regress assumes an absence of common interpretations of the law of nature. A chaotic state of nature implies that it is useless to expect the law of nature or common reason to keep men in order, not only because they have conflicting, interests, but also, more fundamentally, because they can't agree. There is 'no common Rule of Good and Evill' and so the buck of interpreting the law of nature has to stop somewhere other than 'the people'. The: 'unwritten Law of nature' is denied any practical efficacy apart from dictating the need for a sovereign and any other content it may be given by state power, whose right 'and, further, duty it is to interpret and enforce it (Lev. 120 / 24, 322-3 / 142-3).21 Partiality is not, as iI1 Milton! and Locke, an unfortunate possibility which may prevent justice being i done, but is so pervasive that the law of nature 'is now become of all laws the most obscure; and has consequently the greatest need of able Interpreters'." It is the sovereign who determines who is an able interpreter: 'The Interpretation of the Law of Nature, is the sentence of the Judge constituted by the Soveraign Authority, to heare and determine such controversies, as' depend thereon.' Without this determination by the sovereign power there would be 'no end of such Inter pretation'. Natural law (what is right according to reason) is dissolved into positive law (the actual, written laws of a state), which denies it any effective independent content while claiming its moral force (Lev. 322-3 f 143, 326 / 145, 120 / 24).(22) Consequently, once out of the state of nature, freedom, which is mere absence of impediment, consists only in what the sovereign is prepared to allow:
(264 / 109)
[27] these politics as non-modern. An example is Stanley Fish's acceptance of Francis Barker's characterization of the 'modern settlement' in terms of a distinction between public and private realms, combined with a denial of the applicability of these terms to Milton, in whose writings.
Milton's insistent
denunciation of idolatry in relation to the office of king is in large
part grounded in this tradition. For example, Milton rejoices in the
fact that although Charles might have thought he could, 'scape unquestionable,
as a thing divine' he discovered that 'the equal and impartial hand
of justice' found him 'no more to spare then another ordinary man' (Tenure,
CPW 3.214, 234; see also Readie, CPW 7.426). This echoes a phrase to
be found in Calvin, among others: 'if a king or prince or magistrate
conducts himself in such a way as to diminish the honour and right of
God, he becomes nothing more than an ordinary: man'.(27) Milton cites
opinions from a number of Protestant divines at the end of Tenure, including
Luther, Zwingli, Bucer and Christopher
(italics mine; CPW 3.250)
Nonetheless, there is a crucial difference between the position of Milton and Locke and that of radical Calvinism. Louis Dumont
describes Calvinist theories of the state as exemplary models of 'modern artificialism': the given is without inherent value, and is instead subjected to the systematic application of an extrinsic, imposed value.(29) But, as in the case of Hobbes, artificialism --the notion that government is founded in some kind of contract --is not the key issue. Where Hobbes subordinates religion to questions of political expediency, however, Calvinist political theory conceives politics as entirely ancillary to religion. For Goodman, following Calvin, the institution of society, effected by men, is sealed by a covenant with God, exemplified by God's instruction to the Israelites to 'put or constitute a kinge to thee: but who thy Lorde thy God shall chose'.(30) Similarly Samuel Rutherford, despite, unlike Goodman, owing many debts to 'natural-law constitutionalism', is above all concerned with 'something that fallen natural reason could never tell him -the covenant obligations of a godly nation'. Rutherford's overriding concern with these obligations means that for him a godly king 'hath a political resemblance of the King of heavens, being a little god and so is above any one man '.(31) While the given is not sacred per se, government which is not directly contrary to God's Will is an expression of that will since 'kings and gouernors' were 'appoynted of God to preserve his people'. So far is this the case for Goodman that even personally evil rulers, 'so longe as their wikednesse bra[k]eth not out manifestly agaynst God, ad his Lawes', have the same divine right to obedience as 'euil and roughe Maisters'.32 By the same token, the political activity that overthrows an ungodly monarch is a religious duty and is undertaken in order to establish a state which will enforce a particular form of godly discipline. It is held to please God first and man second, or rather, to please man only insofar as it pleases God. Calvin's concern is whether' a king or prince or magistrate conducts himself in such a way as to diminish the honour and right of God', not whether he trespasses on men's right to 'oeconomize, 'invades' their property or disregards their liberty. The resistance which is legitimized in this way is conceived as the work of God. As Christopher Goodman put it in the passage quoted earlier, a bad king is 'punisht by the law of God' and in consequence even though such punishment is meted out by men 'it is not mans but Gods doing'. This duty is couched in terms of contempt for the merely human, above all human reason. Goodman refers to 'vile man' who 'will measure obedience with the crowked lyne of his owne corrupte iudgement, and not with the infallible trueth of Goddes holie worde', dismissing 'corrupt reason' by comparison with God's 'holie Lawes and preceptes'.(33) Even Rutherford, who lays less emphasis on the vileness of man did not [30] consider a merely human concern, such as Charles's imposition of taxation without parliamentary consent in the form of Ship Money, to be sufficient cause for disobedience.(34) In Locke, by contrast, there can be discerned, in Skinner's phrase, 'the modern and strictly political concept: of a moral right of resistance'.(35) It is clear that Milton, too, has crossed this threshold. Although there are appeals to God's will in Tenure, these are, 'as Michael Fixler has noted, restricted to the defence of the killing of the king (that is to say, to the part of the tract which, given that the execution was the act of a minority, was in need of whatever rhetorical weapons were to hand), and any apocalyptic faith in England's destiny as a holy nation is, in the context of other writings of the time, 'conspicuously absent'. Tenure is far removed from the theocratic sectarianism which would claim power 'for the saints exclusively as saints.(36) People have not only a right of resistance but (a matter of emphasis here) a right of changing their government as they see fit. Humans have the power to 'execute '. ..the wrath of God upon evil doers without exception', but God is wrathful in such cases because it is evil to abrogate tyrannically men's natural freedom. Tyrants 'may bee as lawfully depos'd and punish'd, as they were at first elected'. Indeed, since the ruler's authority stems from the people, 'then may the people as oft as they shall judge it for the best, either choose him or reject him, retaine him or depose him though no Tyrant, meerly by the liberty and right: of free born Men, to be govern' d as seems to them best' (Tenure, CPW i 3.198, 202, 206). ',Not only can a ruler be resisted for contravening the will of God ,in matters of religion, he is, simply, accountable to those who have delegated their power to him. This is the language of liberty! and rights, not of sainthood. Milton and Locke legitimize this greater concern with human affairs, and with the right of men to manage their own destiny, by reference to natural law.(37) However, it is important to attend to the substance of this law and the outlook it expresses; if unduly archaic conceptions of the nature of their thought are to be avoided. One such is to be found in Joan Bennett's argument that in his formulation of natural law as the basis of government by consent, Milton owes a specific debt to Hooker.(38) As far as this goes, this is unexceptionable. Hooker was referred to and used by everyone in the seventeenth century, from those Royalists who founded government in an original but irrevocable contract, to the Levellers, who wanted constitutional government selected by regular elections, possibly based on a near-universal male franchise.(39) The presence of some such influence on Locke, who is given to quoting 'the judicious Hooker' at strategic points in his argument, is a commonplace, [31] although there is disagreement about its significance.(40) But the distance between Milton and Hooker (and, equally, between Locke and Hooker) is brought out by Bennett in the very act of bringing them together. According to Bennett, the legacy of Hooker in Milton's thought is such that for Milton only a ruler's violation of the natural order of things could justify revolution on earth.(41) However, not only would it be difficult, empirically, to find many seventeenth-century governments which did not, in Milton's view, contravene natural law, but, further, such an assertion totally excludes that side of .Milton for whom, as discussed earlier, the people may change government as often as they see fit. Keith Staveley is right to say, in his comparison of the myth of the social contract in Hooker and Milton, that 'The difference, and it makes all the difference, is one of emphasis. In Hooker the accent 'is on orderly submission to necessity, in Milton, on constructive actions that are necessary.(42) The key to this difference is the presence in Milton and Locke of epistemological and political individualism, and its absence in Hooker and the scholastic natural law tradition on which he was drawing.(43) For Hooker, 'The general and perpetual voyce of men is as the sentence of God himself. For that which all men have at all times learned, nature herself must needs have taught; and God being the author of nature, her voyce is but his instrument.' Hooker did believe that political society had its foundations in the consent of the people, 'an order expressly or secretly agreed upon, touching the manner of their union in living together'. But the notion of such a decision being 'secretly agreed' is clearly of a piece with the idea that 'to be commanded we do consent, when that societie whereof we are part hath at any time before consented, without revoking the same after by the like universal agreement'. Hooker liked the idea of consent, affirming that 'for manifestation of this their [rulers'] right, and mens more peaceable contentment on both sides, the assent of them who are to be governed, seemeth necessarie', but, as F. J. Shirley recognizes, 'any real exercise of that consent would have horrified him'.(44) This is because the consent of the governed is for him not a precondition of legitimacy and a right to be exercised, but part of the perfection of a Christian commonwealth. Unsurprisingly, as a defender of the status quo of the Elizabethan Church settlement, Hooker was writing not with change in mind but with a conviction of the benign and providential inevitability of hierarchically ordered society as presently constituted. By contrast with this rather static evocation of the wisdom of ages, the will of the people is conceived by Milton and Locke as consisting in an aggregate of epistemologically independent and pointedly [32] individual conclusions. Unity is desirable, but real unity is contrasted with forced incorporation. Rational behaviour consists, not in doing what one is told, but in making up one's own mind. For instance, the opening to The Reason of Church-governement urges the importance of embracing the good 'not of custome and awe, which most men do, but of choice and purpose, with true and constant delight' (Reason, CPW 1.746). This is the impulse which lies behind Milton's famous opinion that 'a man may be a heretic in the truth' if it is not a truth he has arrived at for himself (Area, CPW 2.527), and Locke's assertion that 'The floating of other men's opinions in our brains, makes us not one jot the more knowing, though they happen to be true.(45) Each man must be left to exercise 'his owne leading capacity'. When God gave Adam reason, 'he gave him freedom to choose, for reason is but choosing' (CPW 2.513, 527)'. The ideal is of a host of individually directed, dynamic and spontaneous harmonizations of energy: 'To be still searching what we know not, by what we know, still closing up truth to truth as we find it (for all her body is homogeneal, and proportionall) this is the golden rule in Theology as well as in Arithmetick, and makes up the best harmony in a Church; not the forc't and outward union of cold, and neutrall" and" inwardly divided minds' (CPW 2.551). The political nature of such a position is clear in Locke's great work of epistemology, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Locke inveighs against those who 'taking things upon trust, misemploy their power of assent, by lazily enslaving their minds to the dictates and dominion of others, in doctrines which it, is their duty to examine'. His well-known opposition to the notion that certain truths are innate in us, most famously and extremely expressed in his representation of the human mind as a tabula rasa, 'or blank slate, is at least in part politically motivated. Once certain truths had been declared innate, he opines:
[33]
Of course, as well as grounds for comparison there are important differences between Milton and Locke. Locke is less insistently religious in his rhetoric. He is generally held to have favoured limited monarchy while Milton's sympathies were republican, a side to him which debates in today's Britain may have caused scholars to re-emphasize.(47) Locke is a more sophisticated political thinker than Milton, partly by virtue of entering the debate later. Perhaps most significant is the relative absence in Locke's discourse of assertions regarding the rights of the virtuous over the vulgar. It is impossible to work out, from his texts alone, who has membership of political society (that is to say, without detailed and disputed historical argument about what is meant, in which contexts, by terms such as 'men', 'the people' and 'society').(48) Milton, too, is unspecific on the franchise and on who constitutes 'the people' (though, of course, for both he and Locke, 'the people' is a masculine entity), but his discourse is shot through with a 'classical republican' strain which surfaces not only in his vibrant evocations of public action, above all in Areopagitica, but in his exclusion from political consideration of those lacking sufficient virtue. Central to Milton's political vision was 'the middle class, which produces the greatest number of men of good sense and knowledge of affairs. Of the rest some are turned from uprightness and from their interest in learning their country's laws by excessive wealth" and luxury, and others by want and poverty' (CPW 4: 1.472).(49) Tenure begins by proclaiming that 'none can love freedom heartilie, but good men; the rest love not freedom, but licence' (CPW 3.190). In The Readie and Easie Way to Establish a Free Commonwealth, Milton suggests a sliding scale for the weight of votes which unstably mixes social class and virtue.(50) In the Second Defence
Milton avers that
'Those whose power lies in wisdom, experience, industry, and virtue
will, in my opinion, however small their number be a ' majority.' Milton
is always ready to oppose the qualitative question of merit to the quantitative
logic of election by an aggregate of preferences,
[35]
The significance of this commitment to a self essentially free and capable of self-management is sometimes, surprisingly, overlooked in accounts of mode,n political thought. Marx famously contrasted the heroism of the bourgeois revolution with the unheroic nature of the societies they established, and argued that this was because the danger inherent in such actions necessitated 'self-deceptions' on the part of those who engaged in them. For the French, it was images of the Roman republic, while ...at another stage of development, a century earlier, Cromwell and the English people had borrowed speech, passions and illusions from the Old Testament for their bourgeois revolution. When the real aim had been achieved, when the bourgeois transformation of English society had been accomplished, Locke supplanted Habbakuk." This amounts to a considerable downplaying of the radical side of Locke, aligning him with what is implicitly presented (by virtue of the contrast with Old Testament zeal) a, the more placid, stolid and sober readjustment of 1688 Locke becomes the emblem of the subordination of virtue to self-interest. But this seems an inadequate representation of the outlook of a man who, over a number of years, exposed himself to considerable risks in a revolutionary cause.(58) A better understanding of the motivation for such behaviour is to be gained from the work of Edward Andrews, who criticizes Marx for underestimating the causal role played by self-image (and therefore Ideology) in the Revolution of 1688, and for down playing the continuing importance of self-image to the post-revolutionary middle class, not just as a cover for their interests but as an ideal which could exceed them:
[36] of the unheroic possessive individualist, is misleading. Habbakuk's vision of divine justice and prayer for violent deliverance from tyranny was as present in Locke as in Marx. ..And the solid faith of Habbakuk. ..that 'the righteous man shall live by his faithfulness' combines the self-righteousness and self-assertiveness of the revolutionary rights-claimant. Second, Marx enormously oversimplified in presenting civic humanism to be a form of poetic self-deception necessary to cover the prosaic character of possessive individualism. Perhaps possessive. individualism and civic humanism are not incom- , patible but were in fact combined in the person of Locke and others.
[37] as an ideal self-image
in the name of which the text seeks, as it were, to recruit the reader
to the cause of reason. This underpins a politics quite different to
the kind of narrowly self-interested liberalism one can, in manifest
contradiction of his intentions, construct out of Hobbes's texts.(65)
A tone of indignation runs through the texts of both Milton and Locke.
Legitimate government is that which treats men as rational and adult,
Tyrannical force is that which treats men as slaves, cattle or children.
The imagery of the man capable of rational liberty is perhaps more;
compelling and insistent in Milton than it is in Locke. His is more
obviously a rhetoric of mobilization, hitting a higher rhetorical pitch
in moments of more extreme crisis. Sometimes, in keeping with Marx's
characterization of the revolutionary period, he dons the guise of an
Old Testament-style prophet, as at the end of Readie when he cries 'with
the Prophet, O earth, earth, earth! to tell the very soil it self, what
her perverse inhabitants are deaf to'. The legacy of the classical world
is also frequently evoked. Earlier in Readie, Milton, referring to those
who established the commonwealth, says that their actions and words
'testifi'd a spirit in this nation no less noble and well fitted to
the liberty of a Commonwealth, then in the ancient Greeks and Romans'.
The commonwealth is a matter of pride, as becomes even clearer when
conceived that an "Englishman", much less a "gentleman" should plead for it.' He rejects Filmer's work as
In the Second Treatise he accepts that absolute rulers make laws and have judges to interpret them, but, in terms which are revealing, does not accept that this "amounts to the rule of law: 'this is no more than what every man, who loves his own power, profit, or greatness, may, and naturally must do, keep those animals from hurting or destroying one another who labour and drudge only for his pleasure and advantage' (2T §93). Law not based in the rational apprehension of a law of nature in principle accessible to all is, an insult to the humanity of those ~ expected to live under it. This is not to say, however, that Milton and Locke simply have a rosy picture of human nature. Both Milton and Locke, who consider that to treat a man as though he is incapable of rational self-determination is to insult his human nature and reduce him to the status of an animal, are certainly ready thus to insult those they deem incapable of such responsibility. It often seems that the most important issue is not to describe the nature of political order but to decide, quite bluntly, who is in and who is out, or rather, to lay the basis for such decisions by asserting forcefully that some are in and some are out. Something more seems to be at stake than the ideological masking of self-interest in terms of which Habermas accounts for the exclusivity of the 'bourgeois public sphere'. According to Habermas, the 'constitutional norms' appealed to in the discourses of the public sphere 'implied a model of civil society that by no means corresponded to its reality. . . the "private people" on whose autonomy, socially guaranteed by property, the constitutional state counted just as much as on the educational qualifications of the public formed by these people, were in truth a small minority', while the whole idea of rule by 'the people' meant that 'The public sphere of civil society stood or fell with the principle of universal access.' However, restriction of the franchise' did not necessarily have to be viewed as a restriction of the public sphere itself as long as it could be [39] interpreted as the mere legal ratification of a status attained economically in the private sphere', that is to say, as the recognition not of a privilege granted by virtue of one's heredity, but of a right consequent i upon a position in principle open to all men. Of course, this disregarded. the differential distribution of opportunities to attain such a status, and I so the ideological dimension of the idea of a public sphere consisted .. in this 'identification of domination with its dissolution into pure reason' .(68)
series of manifest terms: for example, the 'worker' is represented in opposition to the bourgeois, the uneducated in opposition to the cultured man, the uncivilized in opposition to the civilized, the mad in opposition to the sane, the child in opposition to the adult.(71) One is reasonable or mad, human or bestial, a part of the political nation i or politically disqualified, equal or an object of contempt. For Locke, 'Madmen' and 'children' cannot be free (the same applies to women, , though for Locke, as for Milton, this goes without saying) because freedom is grounded in a man 'having reason, which is able to instruct him in that law he is to govern himself by, and make him know how far he is left to the freedom bf his own will'. To leave such a being in 'unrestrained liberty' would be 'to thrust him out amongst brutes, and abandon him to, a state as wretched and as much beneath that of man; as theirs". Consequently, they are 'never set free from the government of their parents' (2T §60, 63). Criminals, on the other hand, cast themselves out of community. A man who, 'quitting reason', uses force, 'the way of beasts. . becomes liable to be destroyed' (2T §181). "Through such assertions Locke constructs his audience not as Hobbesian pragmatists of power, caught up .in a no-holds-barred battle for survival, but i as righteous extirpators of immorality. The assumed coherence of men! which derives from their adherence to the law of nature, a 'rule ... of reason and common equity, which is that measure God has set to the actions of men for their common security', implies that those incapable of such lawfulness are either subject to eternal surveillance or thrust out: of human community by individuals who, although perhaps acting in isolation, are nevertheless by virtue of their reason representatives or guardians of that community. Miscreants will deservedly meet an 'executioner of the law of nature' (2T §8). Universal ideals legitimize the denial of liberty to those who cannot, and the use of force against those: who will not, recognize them (or recognize themselves in them), and create by contrast a community of the just. Similarly, Milton's Tenure opens with the assertion that 'none can love freedom heartilie,but good men; the rest love not freedom, but licence' (CPW 3.190). The process of definition continues when Milton counsels that 'milde and tender dispositions' avoid being 'foolishly softened from thir duty and perseverance, with the unmaskuline Rhetorick of any; puling Priest or Chaplain' (CPW 3.195). As is suggested by Milton's connection of liberty to the right to 'oeconomize ...as Maisters of Family" (CPW 3.236)} this is business for hardened men, not whining women [41] written to perform begins when he considers the rational basis of kingship. For Milton, 'he that bids a man reigne over him above Law, may bid as well a savage beast'. Indeed, he says, there is: '
holding a place by virtue of one's birth, to an assertion that the king holds his place not by birth but by virtue of an agreement of the people, which is to say by 'Law' and by 'all the Covnants and Oaths that gave him title to his dignity', because they signified an 'alliance' with his people.(72) These are, as Milton goes on to say, 'the onely tie of our obedience to him.(73) Milton then, as Merritt Hughes points out, describes the brotherhood of all men in words which 'invoke the principle of a universal human society resting upon man's gift of reason and dictating a just law of nations, as Cicero repeatedly affirmed' (CPW 3.214 i n87). This is a model example of the way history can imbue ideas with ~ active significance. When Milton evokes Cicero, he is evoking more' than an ideal or aspiration, since he does so in the context of Puritanism's internationalist thrust and draws the conclusion that this bond implies duties to be fulfilled overseas. This text is 'a part of the Puritan invention of politics, if politics is defined not as the stuff of intrigue and 'faction' but as a programme aimed at changing the world so that it conforms to reason.(74) But in the midst of this internationalism, it becomes clear that the bond of universal fellowship is consituted by a force of exclusion so powerful that it questions the usual Protestant i order of things. To behave unreasonably or offensively is to be expelled I from the community of man as a representative of the (supposedly) barbaric Orient, menacing what becomes, by contrast, and rather surprisingly in the light of Milton's views on Catholicism, a more or less; Christian Europe.(75) The coherence of this Europe could take on quite material forms, such as military cooperation. Milton himself wrote on behalf of Cromwell to Catholic rulers asking them to unite with other Christians against the Turk.(76) Milton is caught up and active in the cultural project whereby 'European political thinkers in the age of Absolutism repeatedly sought' to define the character of their own world by opposition with that of the Turkish order.'(77) Although the main thrust of the text seems to be to undermine the claims of nativity, and although, in its applicability to Charles, the term 'Turk' is clearly not conceived in exclusively racial terms, it would seem that nativity --or race --nevertheless grounds and defines what might otherwise be a limitless community of men. This is implicit in the ghostly coherence of Europe, but also, with much more apparent solidity, in the notion of being English. Nationhood, it appears, is first and foremost a natural fact: a nation is the place where I one is born. Certainly, while a covenant is the only tie that binds the English people and their king, the ties that bind the English people to one another can simply be assumed. There is a 'brotherhood between
man and man allover the World', but 'a straiter bond yet...between fellow-subjects, neighbours, and friends'. So much can simply be assumed. Certainly there is no mention of nationality having a basis in a covenant. One can be excluded, in the light of the universal law of nature, regardless of how 'native' one is, but this formulation does not, challenge the fact of nativity. In fact it seems that the law of nature in this passage polices the boundaries of a naturally given community.(78) Tenure disqualifies Charles, by virtue of his ungodly pride, from membership of both the English nation and European Christendom. He is in a position analogous to that of the 'Wen' (Milton's image for episcopacy) in Of Reformation, an excremental impurity which must be cut off to leave the 'lawfull and free-borne members' whole and clean, and i to reaffirm England as an example of 'liberty and the flourishing deeds i of a reformed Common-wealth... wherein we have the honour to precede other Nations who are now labouring to be our followers' (CPW 1.583-4). Through his execution in the name of the 'mutual bond of amity' that unites all men, England leads the way to freedom, presumably leaving behind 'the people of Asia', who are 'much inclinable to slavery' (CPW 3.202-3).
that 'a Commonwealth
ought to be but as one huge Christian personage, one mighty growth,
and stature of an honest man, as big, and compact in vertue as in body'
(CPW 1.572). The trial of Charles by the Independents, which Tenure
was written to justify, was characterized, as Andrew Milner notes, by
a marked indifference to technical legality, since they felt themselves
to be concerned simply with justice.(81) But' Milton's political discourse
is too early and inchoate to be meaningfully categorized in'this way.
There is too much emphasis on virtue for him to be described as a liberal,
but Milton is too preoccupied with freedom,' and a natural law which
transcends positive institutions for him consistently to view any organization
as embodying such principles absolutely. Nonetheless, the intimate link
in both Milton and Locke between a community of rational individuals
and a drive to expel those who do not conform to the norms of rationality
might well incline us to favour. Foucault's response to Habermas's search
for consensus: 'The farthest I would go is to say that perhaps one must
not be for consensuality, but one must be against nonconsensuality.(82)
Despite manifesting a principled wariness of any particular positive
consensus, such caution about siding with the majority nonetheless presupposes
the i desirability of consent, an ethos intrinsic to the notion of the
self as a bearer of rights, the expansion of which is inseparable from
the modern, discursive regime Milton and Locke helped to impose.(83)
|
||
![]() |
|